Difference between revisions of "OCT 10"

From Alfino
Jump to navigationJump to search
(Created page with "==13: OCT 10: Some Cultural Evolutionary Theory== ===Assigned=== :*Henrich, Joe. Prelude and Chapter 1, "WEIRD Psychology" from ''The WEIRDEST People in the World'' (21-58)...")
 
m
 
Line 1: Line 1:
==13: OCT 10: Some Cultural Evolutionary Theory==
+
==14: OCT 10. Unit Two (Part two): Models of morality from moral psychology==
  
 
===Assigned===
 
===Assigned===
  
:*Henrich, Joe. Prelude and Chapter 1, "WEIRD Psychology" from ''The WEIRDEST People in the World'' (21-58)
+
:*Churchland C5 – “I’m just that way” – (110-126; 16) – neurology and moral personality, political attitudes.
  
:*Rawls' Theory of Justice
+
===In-Class===
::*16 minute video focused on Rawls: [https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=n6k08C699zI&feature=youtu.be].
 
::*6 minute video, PBS series: [https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=H0CTHVCkm90&feature=youtu.be]
 
  
===In-class===
+
:*The Paradox of Moral Experience.
 +
:*Issue Commitment v Political Orientation
 +
:*Conversational Strategies for Engaging Political Difference
  
:*Rawls' Theory of Justice
+
==='''Paradox of Moral Experience'''===
:*Meet Joe Henrich, Cultural Evolutionary Theorist [https://henrich.fas.harvard.edu/]
 
:*Back evaluations - '''Due this Friday!!'''
 
:*SW1 Review Exercise - 5 points.  (No late submissions without prior notice.)
 
  
===SW1 Review - 5 Points===
+
::*The Paradox of Moral Experience involves a conflict between two "standpoints" for seeing values.  Roughly, we experience our moral positions as our "truths", but when we study morality using social science methods (objective, 3rd person), our positions look "caused". 
  
:*In addition to completing back-evaluations, I would like you to review some high scored papers and compare your comments and scores with your peers.  If you do that and report it on this [https://docs.google.com/forms/d/e/1FAIpQLSc7Nu8Tbgiy2m3RpYA8YJz0svcSoxxxJMHkT67oqXw_dfMQ4A/viewform?usp=sf_link form], you will receive 5 points.
+
:The two standpoints:
:*This assignment is due by '''Thursday, October 12, at midnight'''.
 
  
===Henrich, "WEIRD Psychology," from The Weirdest People on Earth"===
+
::*1. We '''experience our morality''' as beliefs we hold true. They are compelling to us in a way that leads us to expect others to find them compelling. We can be surprised or frustrated that others do not see our reasons as compelling.  From this standpoint, our moral truths feel '''necessary rather than contingent'''. 
 +
:::*Examples: "What's wrong with those (lib/con)s, don't they see X/Y?" "How can anyone think it's ok to act like that?") 
  
:*'''Prelude: Your Brain has been modified by culture'''
+
::*2. But, when we '''study morality objectively, as a functional system''' that integrates people who see and interpret the world differently, it is less surprising that we often do not find each others' reasoning or choices compelling.  We can also see how groups of people might develop "values cultures" that diverge on entire sets of values (or, "cooperative toolkits") while still solving some of the same underlying problems that all human societies face.  From this standpoint, the functions of morality are universal, but the specific strategies that individuals and cultures take seem very contingent. But, knowing this, why don’t we experience our own values as contingent?
 +
:::*Examples: Sociocentric / Individualist cultures, Specific histories that groups experience (Us vs. Europe vs. ...)
  
::*Example of how reading alters brains.  "Literacy thus provides an example of how culture can change people biologically independent of any genetic differences."
+
:*Some implications:
::*The ‘letterbox’ in your brain
+
::*We have a bias against seeing others' moral beliefs as functional.  Rather, we see them as caused, and often wrongheaded(Italians are more sociocentric because their culture makes them that wayRather than, sociocentric culture functions to solve basic problems, just like individualistic ones in more ind cultures.)
::*Literacy in Western Europe - a “cultural package” that includes abilities, but also attitudes toward education, technologies of literacy like printing.   
+
::*Different moral "matrices" are connected to our personality and identityAreguing for the truth of your moral orientation (as opposed to focusing on issues) can be like telling someone they shouldn't be the people they are. (!)
::*Note how a “culture of literacy” can cut across other culturesRight hemisphere bias in facial recognition common to university students across cultures.
 
::*1517: Protestantism requires literacy.  "sola scriptura"
 
::*Showing causal relationship with "quasi-experimental" method  "For every 100 km traveled from Wittenberg, percentage of Protestants dropped 10%. Like a "dosage".  Also drove female literacy and public education.   
 
::*Also seen in literacy rates of Catholic and Prot missionaries to Africa: Protestant missions produce more literacy. 
 
::*Point of his book, “The WEIRDEST People in the World,”: WEIRD psychology is the result of a set of cultural adaptations promoted by the Catholic church.
 
::*The movement of “sola scriptura” led to an explosion of literacy, which had numerous cultural effects, but the bigger story of how we became WEIRD starts with the Catholic Churches’ “Marriage and Family Plan” (Chapter 1).
 
  
:*'''Chapter 1: WEIRD Psychology'''
+
===Churchland C5 – “I’m just that way” – (110-126; 16)===
  
::*WEIRD: individualistic, self-obsessed, control-oriented, nonconformist, and analytical.  Tends to look for universal categories, analytic.  patient, takes plesure in hard work, sticks to imparial rules or principles, guilt vs. shame
+
:*Do personality traits partially determine how we decide something is right or wrong? 
 +
:*Is political orientation partially determined by personality?
 +
:*Is personality partiality determined by genes?
 +
:*If the answers are yes, yes, and yes, what are the implications?
  
::*Major Claim: WEIRD psychology is a product of 600-1000 years of the Catholic Church's modification of our psychology through its "Marriage and Family Plan".
+
:*111: Neuorological response to negative stimuli, such as rotting carcases or someone eating live worms correlates significantly with political orienation (as measured by Wilson-Patterson Attitude Inventory).
  
:*'''Really, who are you?'''
+
:*2014 study by Woo-Young Ahn - even response to one image is enough for better than chance prediction of political orientationInterestingly little correlation with reported (Sys 2) rating of imagesIt's Sys 1 that betrays us...
::*"Who Am I? task by culture
 
::*Mapping the Individualism Complex vs. Kin-based institutions
 
:::*Might be ''obligated'' to avenge a murder,
 
:::*''Prohibited'' from marrying a stranger / ''privileged'' to marry mother’s brother’s daughters.
 
:::*''Responsible'' to carry out expensive ancestor rituals.
 
:::*''Liable'' for family members crimes.
 
:::*Note the italicized moral terms.  Moral culture changes with sociocentrism/individualism, as in Haidt.   
 
::*Contrast on p. 28.  In the Industrial World "everyone is shopping for better relationships." Read specific contrasts.   
 
::*Hofstede's scale for measuring individualism/sociocentrism -
 
::*Economic prosperity and Individualism may be in two way causal relationship.
 
::*Note caveats to this research on p. 31.  1. As with physio-politics, '''not''' say one cultural package is objectively better than another. [Arguably, individualism and markets got us to the crisi of climate change.] 2. As with physio-politics, the categories mask numerous continuous differences.
 
  
:*'''Cultivating the WEIRD self'''
+
:*Work of Hibbing (see especially Chapters 5 and 6 from previous course readings).  Physio-politics: Attentaional studies, Electrodermal studies (EDM or skin conductivity)
::*Research showing individualists cultivate "consistency across relationships" vs. kin-based "consistency within relationships”.
+
::*Gaze cueing studies - liberals more influenced by gaze cues.
::*Dispositionalism - seeing people's behavior as anchored impersonal traits that influence actions across contexts. The Fundamental Attribution Error (33) is a bias of WEIRD people, not a universal cognitive bias.  WEIRD people suffer more from cognitive dissonance because of the type of consistency valued in WEIRD culture.
+
::*Eye tracking - conservatives lock on to negative or threatening faces faster, longer dwell time.
::*Guilt vs. Shame
+
::*Cognitive tests - soft categorizers v hard categorizers, Beanfest!
::*Conformity - Solom Asch's experiments in which confederates give incorrect answers to test conformity.  WEIRD cultures show lowest conformity. 37-38.
+
::*From Churchland also, p. 116.
  
:*'''Marshmallows Come to Those Who Wait'''
+
:*Heritability of moral personality and political attitudes.
::*"Discounting" as a measure of '''patience''' - "temporal discounting" widely researched through "choice" studies: "Would you rather X now or X+Y later?"  Patience correlated with better socio-economic outcomes. Larger construct: "self-control" "self-regulation - Marshmallow studies.  [https://youtu.be/QX_oy9614HQ]
+
::*MZ (identical) and DZ (fraternal) twin studies show this for traits such as personality traits like aggressiveness, traditionalism, obedience to authority.   
::*'''Impersonal Honesty''' --
+
::*Also for political attitudes.   
:::*UN Diplomats' parking violations research.  Natural experiment on existing parking violations.  Volume of tickets correlates with country's standing on "corruption index". 
+
::*Extroversion, openness to new experience, emotional stability (neuroticism), agreeablenessNote: These are results in personality theory and research broadly[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Big_Five_personality_traits]
:::*Impersonal Honesty Game, like the Matrix research from Ariely, normed against probability of each die roll. Also correlates with corruption index. (results at p. 44).  "quintessentially WEIRD experiment as there is no person affected by the dishonesty.  In some cultures, you would be criticized for not taking advantage of the experiment to help your family.  
 
::*'''Universalism and Non-relationalism''' -- Research using the "Passengers Dilemma" -- does your friend have a right to expect you to lie to help him evade a parking fine? related results: willingness to give insider information, lie about medical exam to lower insurance rates, write a fake review of a friend's restaurant. Measures also importance of '''impartial rules'''
 
::*'''Trusting Strangers''' - "Generalized Trust Question" (GTQ) survey instrument.  measures impersonal trust vs. trust in relationship based networks.  Norway: 70% Trinidad 4-5% Interesting variation in the US.  Northern Italy 49% Sicily 26%.  [Interesting discussion of forms of trustCountries can report high trust on the GTQ, but it may not be impersonal trust.  To get at that you have to ask specifically about trusting strangers.]
 
::*'''Impersonal Prosociality'''  roughly, "how we feel toward a person who is not tied into our social network" - correlated with national wealth, better government, less corruption, faster innovation.   
 
::*'''Obsessed with intentions''' -- Bob/Rob and Andy vignette research.  The "Bob" condition involves intent.  Barrett and Laurence research.  Focus on intentional dishonesty correlates with WEIRD culture.  Independent research on Japanese (less focused on intentions), suggests that other factors about Japan's culture affect outcomes.
 
::*'''Analytic vs. Holistic thinking'''.  Triad Task.  (read 53) Abstract rule-based vs. Functional relationship. Analytics focus on rules, types, continuity. Example: Would you match "rabbit" with "carrot" or "cat"? Possible that even some of the Mapuche's "analytic" answers had holistic reasoning.  pig/dog pig/husks.  Also, attention and memory studies: East Asians remember background/context better that WEIRD people.  Americans track the center of attention. 
 
::*WEIRD also have great '''endowment effect, overestimate our talents, self-enhance, enjoy making choices'''.
 
::*Summary table on p. 56. 
 
  
:*Henrich's larger argument:
+
:*How do heritable personality traits related to political orientation?
::*The Catholic Church, through it "Marriage and Family Plan" (started around 600 a.d.), started the process that made us WEIRDSee Henrich, C14, "The Dark Matter of History" for summary of the book's argument.  (In shared folder.)
+
::*Caveat: Traits are on a spectrumYou can be conservative about some things and liberal about others. But:
::*Movement from kin and clan based European culture, to "voluntary associations (guilds, charter towns, universities) drove the expansion of impersonal markets, and spurred the rapid growth of cities.
+
::*120: Openness predicts less traditional, more liberal.
::*Key elements of the Church's "Marriage and Family Plan"
+
::*Conservatives relatively neophobic, liberals neophilic.
:::*Monogamous marriages only
 
:::*No kin marriage
 
:::*No arranged marriage
 
:::*Neolocal residence (married couples move out of parents' house)
 
:::*Inheritance by testament
 
:::*Individual property
 
:::*No adoption
 
  
===Rawls Theory of Justice ===
+
:*Skepticism about the theory that "instinctive pathogen stress response" underlies outgroup behavior.  This might modify our theorizing about the fart spray experiment (and related results). 
  
::*16 minute video focused on Rawls: [https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=n6k08C699zI&feature=youtu.be].  
+
:*The things we get most worked up about: sexuality, intimacy, treatment of outgroups, might be the parts of our conscience and psychology that are most shaped by evolution. (Note the issues these core challenges map onto: abortion, gay marriage, immigration, war, discrimination.)
::*6 minute video, PBS series: [https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=H0CTHVCkm90&feature=youtu.be]
 
  
:*PBS short video on Rawls
+
===Some ways that our moral personalities show up in everyday life.===
:*Justice as fairness - Ancient Greeks: harmony. Range of goals: liberty, caring for needs, etc.
 
:*Justice is about distribution of goods.  “Distributive justice”. Examples: equality, needs, merit (getting what you deserve), Rawls- Justice is fairness.  Response to natural inequalities.  This is a form of needs based justice.  Life is unfair, justice is a remedy for that.
 
:*Nozick (Libertarian) objects: Wilt Chamberlain thought experiment.  Unjust to even out the playing field.  As long as we don’t get our stuff by unjust means, we deserve our stuff. 
 
:*Negative rights v positive rights. “Freedom from interference” v “Right to some goods”
 
  
:*”Then and Now” video
+
:*In intimate partnerships, we often look for “differences”But there are at least 3 things we look for sameness on in partner choice: religion, political orientation, and drinking behavior.
::*Rawls’ Theory of Justice 1972
 
::*Responding to utilitarian views of justiceCriticism of utilitarianism.  Might not protect rights sufficiently.  Slavery example. 
 
::*Rawls want to mix a rights view with distributive justice. Rights are not directly utilitarian (though possibly indirectly)
 
  
:*Original Social Contract tradition. Another Enlightenment philosophical product!  See [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Social_contract Social Contract wiki].
+
:*Trump fridges v. Biden fridges [https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2020/10/27/upshot/biden-trump-poll-quiz.html]
::*Social contract tradition.  Original position.  '''What rules and principles would it be rational to choose?'''
 
:*Rawls' basic method: Principles of justice should be chosen by following a kind of thought experiment in which you imagine yourself not knowing specific things about your identity and social circumstances.  Adopting this special stance is what Rawls calls the "veil of ignorance" (parallel in Social Contract tradition)
 
:*Original Position in Rawls' thought: Choosing principles of justice under a "veil of ignorance" (simple intuition about fairness: How do you divide the last piece of cake?
 
::*Note how this realizes a basic condition of moral thought: neutrality, universalization, fairness.
 
  
::*In the original position:
+
:*Cons and Libs like: different kinds of sermons, jokes, stories, decor. Cons favor Porsches, Libs Volvos
:::*You still know: human psychology, human history, economics, the general types of possible situations in which humans can find themselves.
 
:::*You don't know: your place in society, your class, social status, for tu in in natural assets and abilities, sex, race, physical handicaps, generation, social class of our parents, whether you are part of a discriminated group, etc.
 
  
::*Note Rawls' argument for choosing things you don't know.  He considers them "morally arbitrary."  You don't deserve to be treated better or worse for your ethnicity, talents, health status, orientation, etc.  Recall historically arbitrary differences like noble birth that we used to treat as morally significant. 
+
===Issue Commitment v Political Orientation===
::*A conservative theorist might object.  If a healthy person can earn more money and the freedom to earn money is a matter of moral consequence, then maybe health isn't morally arbitrary?  On the other hand, you might be hard pressed to claim that you “deserve” more money because you had healthier genes.  For Rawls, it might still be just for you to earn more, but you should also acknowledge that you are benefiting from “morally arbitrary” features of your existence while others are suffering from morally arbitrary deficits.
 
  
:*So, what principles would it be rational to choose?
+
:*To make practical use of this research, we need to introduce a distinction between "issue commitments" (roughly our position on the political questions of the day) vs "political orientation" (our enduring (after age 22-25) cognitive and emotional responses that predict liberal - moderate - conservative).
 +
:*Textbook examples:
 +
::*Pearl Harbor
 +
::*Americans with Disabilities Act
 +
::*Immigration - Bush republicans vs. Trump republicans
  
:*Rawls claims we would choose the following two principles
+
:*Theory Contrast:
::*1) '''Principle of Equal Liberty''': Each person has an equal right to the most extensive liberties compatible with similar liberties for all.  
+
::*Old school thinking -- We decide to be liberal or conservative (under the tutelage of our dear professors). (Enlightenment connection.  Reason is independent of culture. We reason our way to our political orientation.)
::*Basic liberties 11:46. Play.  Freedom from: right to vote, speech, assembly, freedom of thought, property, from arbitrary arrest, from discrimination. Positive: Opportunities, basic education.  (Egalitarian about rights.)
+
::*(Possible) New thinking. Political orientation is:
::*2) '''Difference Principle''': Social and economic inequalities should be arranged so that they are both (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged persons, and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of equality of opportunity. (Welfare principle for distribution of goods.). “Maximin” strategy maximizing the minimum possible position.  Based on a risk calculation. (Note: people have different risk tolerance.  Could be a criticism.) 
+
:::*part of our identity, connected to personality, gels around age 25.  
 +
:::*orientation doesn't change, but issue commitments can.
  
:*The core intuition behind Rawls' approach is that some things are "morally arbitrary".  The veil is an attempt to exclude them.
+
:*Implications:
 +
::*It may be bigotry to think less of someone because they have a different political orientation than you.
 +
 
 +
===Implications from this research for how we interact with others on moral and political values questions - Small Group Discussion===
 +
 
 +
:*In your groups, consider some of the following questions:
 +
::*Should we be more careful about how we interact over political orientation (compare to other identity issues)?
 +
::*Is it bigotry to tell someone or imply to someone that they shouldn't be conservative or liberal?
 +
::*Should we consider new conversational strategies (and values) to accomodate the new research?
 +
::*In light of this research, what is the best way to get someone with a different political orientation than you to agree on your issue commitment?
 +
 
 +
===Conversational Strategies for Engaging Political Difference===
 +
 
 +
:*A big problem that this unit leaves us with is, "How do we interact with people with different matrices and different experiences, especially concerning political value differences, when we hold our own views with conviction and sense of their truth? In other words, how do we deal with the '''Paradox of Moral Experience'''?
 +
 
 +
:*Why this is ''so'' difficult...
 +
::*We often unintentionally (and, for some people, intentionally) create "cognitive dissonance" in a discussion, leading people to find ways to stop the pain, rather than listen to the issues. This can escalate.
 +
::*We don't always have reasons for our convictions, but, as we know from the dumbfounding research, we "confabulate". We confuse intuitions with reasoned conviction.  This can lead us to "pile on" arguments, thinking they are persuasive apart from the intuitions (moral matrix) that support them. But if you don't have those intuitions, the "pile on" can feel aggressive.
 +
::*We don't all react the same way when our views are criticized.  (Remember Socrates' attitude here. Noble but difficult to achieve.)
 +
 
 +
:*'''1. Three Basic Strategies:'''
 +
::*A. Explore differences gently. Monitor your vital signs and those of your interlocutors.
 +
::*B. Find common goals or things to affirm. (Example of landlord interaction last semester.)
 +
::*C. Model exploratory thought. (How do you do that, specifically?)  See ''sympathetic interpretation'' below.
 +
::*These strategies obviously move you in different directions in a conversation, but they can all be used together to manage "dissonance" and tension in a discussion.
 +
 
 +
:*'''2. Practice Sympathetic Interpretation'''
 +
::*In general, sympathetic interpretation involves strategies that mix "identification" (peanuts for the elephant) with "critical engagement" (rational persuasion, expression of value differences)
 +
::*Try to understand where a view is "coming from".  Ask questions.
 +
::*Restate views, checking for fairness.
 +
 
 +
:*'''3. Other miscellaneous strategies''' (many contributed by students):
 +
 
 +
::*Cultivate diverse relationships if possible.
 +
::*Avoid pejorative labels.
 +
::*Views can change even if orientations don't.  Focus on views, not orientations.
 +
::*Accept differences that won't change (validate them in others, as you would other differences), focus on pragmatics and cooperation.
 +
::*Humor, if possible.  Self-effacing humor can set the stage.
 +
::*Acknowledge physio-politics in the discussion.  Give people "permission" or space to "out" themselves as libs and cons.
 +
::*Acknowledge your own orientation and expect it to be respected.
 +
::*Don't "sugar coat" differences.  (Be true to yourself.)
 +
 
 +
===Argumentative and Rhetorical Strategies for Engaging Political Difference===
 +
 
 +
:*Acknowledge partial truths in opposing views, and weaknesses in your own view.
 +
:*Present your issue commitment as something that should appeal to someone with a different political orientation.
 +
:*::*Practice "strategic dissimulation" (controversial for some).  "I'm still working out my views here..." when you really have pretty well worked out views, even one's you are proud of and think to be true (Paradox of Moral Experience)
 +
::*Practice "strategic self-deprecation" - Acknowledge knowledge deficits or evidentiary weaknesses in your view as a way of inviting a more critical discussion.
 +
::*Use verbal cues that indicate (if possible) that views you disagree with are "reasonable" and/or "understandable".  That could mean:
 +
:::*1. The view is reasonable, even if you disagree. Preface your disagreement by acknowledging this. 
 +
::::*Example: "Reasonable and well-informed people disagree on this..."... "Well, your in good company..."
 +
:::*2. The view seems unreasonable, but you focus on some intuitions that support it, even if you don't share these intuitions.
 +
::::*Example: I can see how/why someone would feel this way..., but...
 +
:::*3. The view seems unreasonable and false to you, but it is one that many people hold.
 +
::::*Example: Acknowledging that the view is widely held without endorsing it.  You can also "deflect" to the complexity of the problem or human nature...

Latest revision as of 16:52, 10 October 2024

14: OCT 10. Unit Two (Part two): Models of morality from moral psychology

Assigned

  • Churchland C5 – “I’m just that way” – (110-126; 16) – neurology and moral personality, political attitudes.

In-Class

  • The Paradox of Moral Experience.
  • Issue Commitment v Political Orientation
  • Conversational Strategies for Engaging Political Difference

Paradox of Moral Experience

  • The Paradox of Moral Experience involves a conflict between two "standpoints" for seeing values. Roughly, we experience our moral positions as our "truths", but when we study morality using social science methods (objective, 3rd person), our positions look "caused".
The two standpoints:
  • 1. We experience our morality as beliefs we hold true. They are compelling to us in a way that leads us to expect others to find them compelling. We can be surprised or frustrated that others do not see our reasons as compelling. From this standpoint, our moral truths feel necessary rather than contingent.
  • Examples: "What's wrong with those (lib/con)s, don't they see X/Y?" "How can anyone think it's ok to act like that?")
  • 2. But, when we study morality objectively, as a functional system that integrates people who see and interpret the world differently, it is less surprising that we often do not find each others' reasoning or choices compelling. We can also see how groups of people might develop "values cultures" that diverge on entire sets of values (or, "cooperative toolkits") while still solving some of the same underlying problems that all human societies face. From this standpoint, the functions of morality are universal, but the specific strategies that individuals and cultures take seem very contingent. But, knowing this, why don’t we experience our own values as contingent?
  • Examples: Sociocentric / Individualist cultures, Specific histories that groups experience (Us vs. Europe vs. ...)
  • Some implications:
  • We have a bias against seeing others' moral beliefs as functional. Rather, we see them as caused, and often wrongheaded. (Italians are more sociocentric because their culture makes them that way. Rather than, sociocentric culture functions to solve basic problems, just like individualistic ones in more ind cultures.)
  • Different moral "matrices" are connected to our personality and identity. Areguing for the truth of your moral orientation (as opposed to focusing on issues) can be like telling someone they shouldn't be the people they are. (!)

Churchland C5 – “I’m just that way” – (110-126; 16)

  • Do personality traits partially determine how we decide something is right or wrong?
  • Is political orientation partially determined by personality?
  • Is personality partiality determined by genes?
  • If the answers are yes, yes, and yes, what are the implications?
  • 111: Neuorological response to negative stimuli, such as rotting carcases or someone eating live worms correlates significantly with political orienation (as measured by Wilson-Patterson Attitude Inventory).
  • 2014 study by Woo-Young Ahn - even response to one image is enough for better than chance prediction of political orientation. Interestingly little correlation with reported (Sys 2) rating of images. It's Sys 1 that betrays us...
  • Work of Hibbing (see especially Chapters 5 and 6 from previous course readings). Physio-politics: Attentaional studies, Electrodermal studies (EDM or skin conductivity)
  • Gaze cueing studies - liberals more influenced by gaze cues.
  • Eye tracking - conservatives lock on to negative or threatening faces faster, longer dwell time.
  • Cognitive tests - soft categorizers v hard categorizers, Beanfest!
  • From Churchland also, p. 116.
  • Heritability of moral personality and political attitudes.
  • MZ (identical) and DZ (fraternal) twin studies show this for traits such as personality traits like aggressiveness, traditionalism, obedience to authority.
  • Also for political attitudes.
  • Extroversion, openness to new experience, emotional stability (neuroticism), agreeableness. Note: These are results in personality theory and research broadly. [1]
  • How do heritable personality traits related to political orientation?
  • Caveat: Traits are on a spectrum. You can be conservative about some things and liberal about others. But:
  • 120: Openness predicts less traditional, more liberal.
  • Conservatives relatively neophobic, liberals neophilic.
  • Skepticism about the theory that "instinctive pathogen stress response" underlies outgroup behavior. This might modify our theorizing about the fart spray experiment (and related results).
  • The things we get most worked up about: sexuality, intimacy, treatment of outgroups, might be the parts of our conscience and psychology that are most shaped by evolution. (Note the issues these core challenges map onto: abortion, gay marriage, immigration, war, discrimination.)

Some ways that our moral personalities show up in everyday life.

  • In intimate partnerships, we often look for “differences”. But there are at least 3 things we look for sameness on in partner choice: religion, political orientation, and drinking behavior.
  • Trump fridges v. Biden fridges [2]
  • Cons and Libs like: different kinds of sermons, jokes, stories, decor. Cons favor Porsches, Libs Volvos

Issue Commitment v Political Orientation

  • To make practical use of this research, we need to introduce a distinction between "issue commitments" (roughly our position on the political questions of the day) vs "political orientation" (our enduring (after age 22-25) cognitive and emotional responses that predict liberal - moderate - conservative).
  • Textbook examples:
  • Pearl Harbor
  • Americans with Disabilities Act
  • Immigration - Bush republicans vs. Trump republicans
  • Theory Contrast:
  • Old school thinking -- We decide to be liberal or conservative (under the tutelage of our dear professors). (Enlightenment connection. Reason is independent of culture. We reason our way to our political orientation.)
  • (Possible) New thinking. Political orientation is:
  • part of our identity, connected to personality, gels around age 25.
  • orientation doesn't change, but issue commitments can.
  • Implications:
  • It may be bigotry to think less of someone because they have a different political orientation than you.

Implications from this research for how we interact with others on moral and political values questions - Small Group Discussion

  • In your groups, consider some of the following questions:
  • Should we be more careful about how we interact over political orientation (compare to other identity issues)?
  • Is it bigotry to tell someone or imply to someone that they shouldn't be conservative or liberal?
  • Should we consider new conversational strategies (and values) to accomodate the new research?
  • In light of this research, what is the best way to get someone with a different political orientation than you to agree on your issue commitment?

Conversational Strategies for Engaging Political Difference

  • A big problem that this unit leaves us with is, "How do we interact with people with different matrices and different experiences, especially concerning political value differences, when we hold our own views with conviction and sense of their truth? In other words, how do we deal with the Paradox of Moral Experience?
  • Why this is so difficult...
  • We often unintentionally (and, for some people, intentionally) create "cognitive dissonance" in a discussion, leading people to find ways to stop the pain, rather than listen to the issues. This can escalate.
  • We don't always have reasons for our convictions, but, as we know from the dumbfounding research, we "confabulate". We confuse intuitions with reasoned conviction. This can lead us to "pile on" arguments, thinking they are persuasive apart from the intuitions (moral matrix) that support them. But if you don't have those intuitions, the "pile on" can feel aggressive.
  • We don't all react the same way when our views are criticized. (Remember Socrates' attitude here. Noble but difficult to achieve.)
  • 1. Three Basic Strategies:
  • A. Explore differences gently. Monitor your vital signs and those of your interlocutors.
  • B. Find common goals or things to affirm. (Example of landlord interaction last semester.)
  • C. Model exploratory thought. (How do you do that, specifically?) See sympathetic interpretation below.
  • These strategies obviously move you in different directions in a conversation, but they can all be used together to manage "dissonance" and tension in a discussion.
  • 2. Practice Sympathetic Interpretation
  • In general, sympathetic interpretation involves strategies that mix "identification" (peanuts for the elephant) with "critical engagement" (rational persuasion, expression of value differences)
  • Try to understand where a view is "coming from". Ask questions.
  • Restate views, checking for fairness.
  • 3. Other miscellaneous strategies (many contributed by students):
  • Cultivate diverse relationships if possible.
  • Avoid pejorative labels.
  • Views can change even if orientations don't. Focus on views, not orientations.
  • Accept differences that won't change (validate them in others, as you would other differences), focus on pragmatics and cooperation.
  • Humor, if possible. Self-effacing humor can set the stage.
  • Acknowledge physio-politics in the discussion. Give people "permission" or space to "out" themselves as libs and cons.
  • Acknowledge your own orientation and expect it to be respected.
  • Don't "sugar coat" differences. (Be true to yourself.)

Argumentative and Rhetorical Strategies for Engaging Political Difference

  • Acknowledge partial truths in opposing views, and weaknesses in your own view.
  • Present your issue commitment as something that should appeal to someone with a different political orientation.
    • Practice "strategic dissimulation" (controversial for some). "I'm still working out my views here..." when you really have pretty well worked out views, even one's you are proud of and think to be true (Paradox of Moral Experience)
  • Practice "strategic self-deprecation" - Acknowledge knowledge deficits or evidentiary weaknesses in your view as a way of inviting a more critical discussion.
  • Use verbal cues that indicate (if possible) that views you disagree with are "reasonable" and/or "understandable". That could mean:
  • 1. The view is reasonable, even if you disagree. Preface your disagreement by acknowledging this.
  • Example: "Reasonable and well-informed people disagree on this..."... "Well, your in good company..."
  • 2. The view seems unreasonable, but you focus on some intuitions that support it, even if you don't share these intuitions.
  • Example: I can see how/why someone would feel this way..., but...
  • 3. The view seems unreasonable and false to you, but it is one that many people hold.
  • Example: Acknowledging that the view is widely held without endorsing it. You can also "deflect" to the complexity of the problem or human nature...